By Thomas Neuburger
In the capitalistic hierarchy of values, capital stands higher than labor, amassed things higher than the manifestations of life. Capital employs labor, and not labor capital. The person who owns capital commands the person who “only” owns his life, human skill, vitality and creative productivity. “Things” are higher than man. —Erich Fromm, The Sane Society
There must be in-groups whom the law protects but does not bind, and out-groups whom the law binds but does not protect. —Frank Wilhoit, defining conservatism as a political philosophy
By a roundabout route, starting with a very good piece from The Lever on the next abortion battle (and it’s going to be a big one), to Cory Doctorow’s reflections on the latest poisonous modern aristocrat (Barre Seid), to a reflection on modern liberalism at Crooked Timber, I landed in my reading on a brilliant comment by composer Frank Wilhoit. This piece is about his comment.
Let me set the stage. The latest conventional wisdom is that America is a divided nation, and those divisions are best expressed as those on the Right (elected Republicans and their supporters) opposing those to the left of those on the Right (elected Democrats and their supporters). The former are usually called “conservatives” — when they’re not being called “fascists” — and the latter are usually labeled “liberals,” or sometimes “progressives” if "liberal” is deemed too tame.
The definition of “conservatism”
An earlier essay on conservatism by UCLA professor Philip Acre, one much read in Bush II years, held that “Conservatism is the domination of society by an aristocracy,” and thus the goals of conservatives are to make the status quo “seem permanent and timeless” and “to pass on their positions of privilege to their children.”
This definition conflicts, of course, with the self-declared notions of conservatism as protectors of “freedom,” but the notion of freedom in conservatism is confused and easy to rebut, starting with the arguments in Agre’s essay itself, and ending with the self-evident arguments made by the actions of our “conservative” Supreme Court, whose definition of freedom seems to start with their freedom to tell you what do, and ends ... right there.
Which leads us to Wilhoit’s comment, written as a reader reply to a post at Crooked Timber. Wilhoit’s main point (lightly edited; emphasis mine):
Conservatism consists of exactly one proposition, to wit:
There must be in-groups whom the law protects but does not bind, alongside out-groups whom the law binds but does not protect.
There is nothing more or else to it, and there never has been, in any place or time.
So far, we’re more or less in agreement with Acre. But Wilhoit has more. He opens this way:
There is no such thing as liberalism — or progressivism, etc. There is only conservatism. No other political philosophy actually exists; by the political analogue of Gresham’s Law, conservatism has driven every other idea out of circulation.
There might be, and should be, anti-conservatism; but it does not yet exist. What would it be? In order to answer that question, it is necessary and sufficient to characterize conservatism. Fortunately, this can be done very concisely.
Stop here, dear reader, and ask yourself the question Wilhoit asked. If there is a thing called “conservatism,” and if it is well defined by both Acre and Wilhoit, what’s its opposite? Liberalism? Progressivism? Socialism? FDR socialism? Social democracy? Something else?
What is the genuine opposite of conservatism, if conservatism is the determination by one group to create an aristocracy that converts money to power (as David Graeber put it in The Dawn of Everything) and uses that power to control other people?
What is the true, mathematically opposite, anti-conservative position?
Give up? Read on.
The definition of “anti-conservatism”
The answer is in the definition of conservatism itself, and is indeed its mathematical (actually, logical) opposite. If conservatism is the creation of a state where, under law, some are bound and not protected, and others are protected and not bound, then anti-conservatism must be
the proposition that the law cannot [be allowed to] protect anyone unless it binds everyone, and cannot [be allowed to] bind anyone unless it protects everyone.
Simple, yes? Yet no, not simple at all.
Which of our proposed better-than-conservative societies — liberal democracy, socialism, social democracy, “FDR socialism” — does not enshrine the unchallenged right of some to exercise power, gained through wealth, over others?
All are flavors of capitalism, all are sweetened subjugation, modified despotism. All soften the destructive effects of billionaire-controlled corporations and allied institutions — like “charities” (search for Bill Gates) and government — so that many suffer less than they would otherwise have done, and few suffer more.
Does that make these institutions — social democracies; liberal democracies — better? Does it make them, like conservative regimes, bad, or evil? As Graeber and Wengrow wrote in The Dawn of Everything, when answering the question “Are humans innately good or innately evil?” they replied:
‘Good’ and ‘evil’ are purely human concepts. It would never occur to anyone to argue about whether a fish, or a tree, were good or evil, because ‘good’ and ‘evil’ are concepts humans made up in order to compare ourselves with one another.
None of these institutions is good nor bad. Do some cause less pain than others? Obviously yes. But to call socialism or any of its cousins “the answer” or “the antidote” to conservatism is to mistake these regimes for what they are not, and to mislead others to make the same mistake.
All of these regimes are flavors of capitalism. And this, from Erich Fromm, is capitalism at its core, modified or not, softened or not, sweetened or the bitter root:
The use of man by man is expressive of the system of values underlying the capitalistic system. Capital, the dead past, employs labor―the living vitality and power of the present. In the capitalistic hierarchy of values, capital stands higher than labor, amassed things higher than the manifestations of life. Capital employs labor, and not labor capital. The person who owns capital commands the person who “only” owns his life, human skill, vitality and creative productivity. “Things” are higher than man. The conflict between capital and labor is much more than the conflict between two classes, more than their fight for a greater share of the social product. It is the conflict between two principles of value: that between the world of things, and their amassment, and the world of life and its productivity. [bolded emphasis mine]
That those who control things control those who control life ... is an abomination. The opposite should be true, yet hasn’t been since the earliest temple-states, the very first city-states days.
Is it a natural condition, a natural state, the domination of men by men, of humans by their equals? Our species has been on this planet for perhaps 200,000 years. The earliest oppressor states, less than a fifth of that. Ninety-five percent of human history is lost, so it’s a separate project to answer that question well.
But if it’s not our natural species state — and I’m inclined, positive soul that I am, to believe that humans have simply become simply “stuck” (Graeber’s term) in just one of a large variety of alternative social structures — then we could become “unstuck” as easily as we stuck ourselves, could rise as easily as fall.
If "stuck" in the current social order is not our natural state, we could free ourselves indeed of an order that hands power to money. We could relaunch our destiny, reboot our social OS to a saner state, and live in a way that’s truly anti-conservative.
Older others have lived far better than us — Stone Age others if Graeber is correct. If they, "mere cavemen," could retain their freedom through most of our hidden past, why not their putative smarter cousins, we? I ask in all sincerity.
A REALLY interesting, yet fairly obvious observation.
200K years ago, all humans were, more or less, struggling for survival, against nature. clan leaders could as easily freeze to death, fail to find food or be subject to predation as anyone else. working together and sharing became important for the survival of the clan and, thus, the species.
However, as societies became more "sophisticated", the limbic urges were never bred out of the species. Thus, greed, lust, the impulse to hoard, fear and hate remained primary impulses. Conservatism is the practice of following one's limbic urges over reason.
Capitalism is the victory of greed over reason. Altruism is a nice idea but is not practiced except on limited levels by thos…